Definition 5.1. A unitary category is
called solvable if the following axiom
is satisfied:
Proposition 5.2. Any spectral category is solvable. Proof. Since any spectral category is unitary by (4.13), we only need to verify Axiom A0. Suppose a and b are two ideals of an object Y and f: Y --> X is an arrow such that f(a) and f(b) are invertible. If f(a b) is non-invertible then it is contained in a prime ideal p by (4.14.a). Then a b is contained in f-1(p). Since f-1(p) is prime, it contains a or b, which means that p contains f(a) and f(b). But this is absurd as p is proper while f(a) and f(b) are invertible. This implies that we must have f(a b) is invertible. Thus the category is solvable. Proposition 5.3. Let C be a solvable
radical category. Then
Proof. Note that (a) is a special case of (b) with f = 1X.
Proposition 5.4. Suppose C is a radical category. Then Axiom A0 is equivalent to (5.3.b). Proof. We only need to verify that (5.3.b) implies Axiom A0 because the other direction is given by (5.3). Suppose f: Y --> X is an arrow and a and b are two ideals of Y such that f(a) and f(b) are invertible. Then (5.3.b) implies that r(f(a b)) = r(f(a)) r(f(b)) = 1X 1X = 1X . Applying (3.8) this means that f(a b) is invertible. Let C be a solvable radical category. For any object X consider the set Ir(X) of radical ideals of X. Suppose f: Y --> X is an arrow. Then f induces a mapping fr: Ir(Y) --> Ir(X) sending each radical ideal a of Y to the radical ideal r(f(a)) of X, which is the left adjoint of the mapping f-1: Ir(X) --> Ir(Y) sending each radical ideal b of Y to the radical ideal f-1(b) of Y. Thus fr preserves join and f-1 preserves meet. Applying (3.6) and (5.3) we obtain Proposition 5.5. (a) r:
I(X) --> Ir(X) preserves
joins and finite meets in a solvable radical category.
Proposition 5.6. Suppose C is a
solvable radical category. Then
Proof. (a) Since Ir(X) is a complete lattice, we verify the infinite distributive law for Ir(X). Suppose a and {bi}are radical ideals of X. We only need to verify that a (ri bi) ri (a bi), where r is the join operation in Ir(X), because the other direction is trivial. Consider a morphism f: Y --> X such that fr(a (ri bi)) is invertible. Then fr(a) and fr( (ribi)) are invertible. Applying (5.5.b) we see that (b) follows from (a) and (5.5.b). Proposition 5.7. Any irreducible ideal p of an object in a solvable radical category is prime. Proof. Since p is a proper radical ideal of X, f-1(p) is a proper radical ideal of Y. Now consider two ideals a and b of Y such that a b f-1(p). Then f(a b) p. Since p is radical we have r(f(a b)) r(p) = p. By (5.3.b) we have r(f(a)) r(f(b)) = r(f(a b)) p. But p is prime, thus r(f(a)) or r(f(b)) is in p. Thus f-1(r(f(a)) or f-1(r(f(b)) is in f-1(p). But a f-1(r(f(a)) and b f-1(r(f(b)). Thus a or b is in f-1(p) . Proposition 5.8. Any maximal ideal in a solvable category is prime. Proof. Suppose m is a maximal ideal of an object X. Then there is an arrow t: X --> Z such that m = ker(t). Suppose f: Y --> X is an arrow and a, b are two ideals of Y not contained in the proper ideal f-1(m). Then f*(a) + m = 1X = f*(b) + m. Thus (tf)*(a) + t*(m) = 1Z = (tf)*(b) + f*(m), i.e. (tf)*(a) = 1Z = (tf)*(b). Hence (tf)*(a b) = 1Z by Axiom A0. This means that a b is not in f-1(m). Thus f-1(m) is prime. Corollary 5.9. A solvable category is spectral if any non-terminal object has an irreducible (or maximal) ideal. Proposition 5.10. Any simple object in a solvable category is integral. Proof. This follows from (5.8). Definition 5.11. An simple and integral object is called a field . Proposition 5.12. (a) A category is spectral
if for any non-terminal object there is an arrow to a integral object (or
field).
Proof. (a) If the condition is satisfied then any non-terminal
object has a prime ideal because the 2-kernel of any arrow to a
integral object is prime.
Proposition 5.13. Suppose C is
a category in which any pair of parallel arrows has a coequalizer and any
such coequalizer has a kernel pair. Suppose T is any object and
(X, t) is an object in T/C.
Proof. (a) If a is an ideal of (X, t) denote by
F*(a) the ideal of X generated by all the
2-elements (F(r), F(s)) where (r,
s) is any 2-element in a. We obtain a map F*:
I((X, t)) --> I(X), which is clearly
injective. Consider any ideal b of X. For any 2-element
(r, s) in b let (r', s'): Z --> X be the kernel
pair of the coequalizer of (r, s). Denote by d: X -->
Z be the diagonal arrow induced by the identities (1X,
1X). Then (Z, dt) is an object of T/C
and (r', s') may be viewed as a 2-element of (X, t).
Denote by a' the ideal generated by all such (r', s')
. It is easy to see that F*(a') = b.
This shows that F* is a natural bijection.
|